Skip to main content

Section 2.3 Techniques for Proving Conditional Propositions

Each of the theorems that we proved in Section 2.1 are examples of conditional propositions. However, some of the statements were disguised as such. For example, Theorem 2.3 states, “The sum of two consecutive integers is odd.” We can reword this theorem as, “If \(n\in\mathbb{Z}\text{,}\) then \(n+(n+1)\) is odd.”

Problem 2.47.

Reword Theorem 2.7 so that it explicitly reads as a conditional proposition.
Each of the proofs that you produced in Section 2.1 had the same format, which we refer to as a direct proof.
Take a few minutes to review the proofs that you wrote in Section 2.1 and see if you can witness the structure of Skeleton Proof 2.48 in your proofs.
The upshot of Theorem 2.39 is that if you want to prove a conditional proposition, you can prove its contrapositive instead. This approach is called a proof by contraposition.
We have introduced the logical symbols \(\neg\text{,}\) \(\wedge\text{,}\) \(\vee\text{,}\) \(\implies\text{,}\) and \(\logeq\) since it provides a convenient way of discussing the formality of logic. However, when writing mathematical proofs, you should avoid using these symbols.

Problem 2.50.

Consider the following statement: If \(x\in\mathbb{Z}\) such that \(x^2\) is odd, then \(x\) is odd. The items below can be assembled to form a proof of this statement, but they are currently out of order. Put them in the proper order.
  1. Assume that \(x\) is an even integer.
  2. We will utilize a proof by contraposition.
  3. Thus, \(x^2\) is twice an integer.
  4. Since \(x=2k\text{,}\) we have that \(x^2 =(2k)^2 =4k^2\text{.}\)
  5. Since \(k\) is an integer, \(2k^2\) is also an integer.
  6. By the definition of even, there is an integer \(k\) such that \(x=2k\text{.}\)
  7. We have proved the contrapositive, and hence the desired statement is true.
  8. Assume \(x\in \mathbb{Z}\text{.}\)
  9. By the definition of even integer, \(x^2\) is an even integer.
  10. Notice that \(x^2 = 2(2k^2)\text{.}\)
Prove the next two theorems by proving the contrapositive of the given statement.
Suppose that we want to prove some proposition \(P\) (which might be something like \(A\implies B\) or even more complicated). One approach, called proof by contradiction, is to assume \(\neg P\) and then logically deduce a contradiction of the form \(Q\wedge \neg Q\text{,}\) where \(Q\) is some proposition. Since this is absurd, the assumption \(\neg P\) must have been false, so \(P\) is true. The tricky part about a proof by contradiction is that it is not usually obvious what the statement \(Q\) should be.
Proof by contradiction can be useful for proving statements of the form \(A\implies B\text{,}\) where \(\neg B\) is easier to “get your hands on,” because \(\neg(A \implies B)\) is logically equivalent to \(A \wedge \neg B\) (see Corollary 2.41).

Problem 2.55.

Assume that \(x\in\mathbb{Z}\text{.}\) Consider the following proposition: If \(x\) is odd, then 2 does not divide \(x\text{.}\)
  1. Prove the contrapositive of this statement.
  2. Prove the statement using a proof by contradiction.
Prove the following theorem via a proof by contradiction. Afterward, consider the difficulties one might encounter when trying to prove the result more directly. The given statement is not true if we replace \(\mathbb{N}\) with \(\mathbb{Z}\text{.}\) Do you see why?
Oftentimes a conditional proposition can be proved via a direct proof and by using a proof by contradiction. Most mathematicians view a direct proof to be more elegant than a proof by contradiction. When approaching the proof of a conditional proposition, you should strive for a direct proof. In general, if you are attempting to prove \(A\implies B\) using a proof by contradiction and you end up with \(\neg B\) and \(B\) (which yields a contradiction), then this is evidence that a proof by contradiction was unnecessary. On the other hand, if you end up with \(\neg Q\) and \(Q\text{,}\) where \(Q\) is not the same as \(B\text{,}\) then a proof by contradiction is a reasonable approach.
In light of Theorem 2.29, if we want to prove a biconditional of the form \(A\logeq B\text{,}\) we need to prove both \(A\implies B\) and \(B\implies A\text{.}\) You should always make it clear to the reader when you are proving each implication. One approach is to label each subproof with “\((\implies)\)” and “\((\Longleftarrow)\)” (including the parentheses), respectively. Occasionally, you will discover that the proof of one implication is exactly the reverse of the proof of the other implication. If this happens to be the case, you may skip writing two subproofs and simply write a single proof that chains together each step using biconditionals. Such proofs will almost always be shorter, but can be challenging to write in an eloquent way. It is always a safe bet to write a separate subproof for each implication.
When proving each implication of a biconditional, you may choose to utilize a direct proof, a proof by contraposition, or a proof by contradiction. For example, you could prove the first implication using a proof by contradiction and a direct proof for the second implication.
The following theorem provides an opportunity to gain some experience with writing proofs of biconditional statements.
Making learning easy does not necessarily ease learning.
―Manu Kapur, learning scientist