Section 4.4 The Well-Ordering Principle
The penultimate theorem of this chapter is known as the Well-Ordering Principle. As you shall see, this seemingly obvious theorem requires a bit of work to prove. It is worth noting that in some axiomatic systems, the Well-Ordering Principle is sometimes taken as an axiom. However, in our case, the result follows from complete induction. Before stating the Well-Ordering Principle, we need an additional definition.
Definition 4.35.
Let \(A\subseteq \mathbb{R}\) and \(m\in A\text{.}\) Then \(m\) is called a maximum (or greatest element) of \(A\) if for all \(a\in A\text{,}\) we have \(a\leq m\text{.}\) Similarly, \(m\) is called minimum (or least element) of \(A\) if for all \(a\in A\text{,}\) we have \(m\leq a\text{.}\)
Not surprisingly, maximums and minimums are unique when they exist. It might be helpful to review
Skeleton Proof 2.90 prior to attacking the next result.
Theorem 4.36.
If \(A\subseteq \mathbb{R}\) such that a maximum (respectively, minimum) of \(A\) exists, then the maximum (respectively, minimum) of \(A\) is unique.
If the maximum of a set \(A\) exists, then it is denoted by \(\tcboxmath{\max(A)}\text{.}\) Similarly, if the minimum of a set \(A\) exists, then it is denoted by \(\tcboxmath{\min(A)}\text{.}\)
Problem 4.37.
Find the maximum and the minimum for each of the following sets when they exist.
\(\displaystyle \{5,11,17,42,103\}\)
\(\displaystyle \mathbb{N}\)
\(\displaystyle \mathbb{Z}\)
\(\displaystyle (0,1]\)
\(\displaystyle (0,1]\cap \mathbb{Q}\)
\(\displaystyle (0,\infty)\)
\(\displaystyle \{42\}\)
\(\displaystyle \{\frac{1}{n}\mid n\in\mathbb{N}\}\)
\(\displaystyle \{\frac{1}{n}\mid n\in\mathbb{N}\}\cup\{0\}\)
\(\displaystyle \emptyset\)
To prove the Well-Ordering Principle, consider a proof by contradiction. Suppose \(S\) is a nonempty subset of \(\mathbb{N}\) that does not have a least element. Define the proposition \(P(n)\coloneqq\) “\(n\) is not an element of \(S\)” and then use complete induction to prove the result.
Theorem 4.38. Well-Ordering Principle.
Every nonempty subset of the natural numbers has a least element.
It turns out that the Well-Ordering Principle (
Theorem 4.38) and the Axiom of Induction (
Axiom 4.1) are equivalent. In other words, one can prove the Well-Ordering Principle from the Axiom of Induction, as we have done, but one can also prove the Axiom of Induction if the Well-Ordering Principle is assumed.
The final two theorems of this section can be thought of as generalized versions of the Well-Ordering Principle.
Theorem 4.39.
If \(A\) is a nonempty subset of the integers and there exists \(l\in \mathbb{Z}\) such that \(l\leq a\) for all \(a\in A\text{,}\) then \(A\) contains a least element.
Theorem 4.40.
If \(A\) is a nonempty subset of the integers and there exists \(u\in \mathbb{Z}\) such that \(a\leq u\) for all \(a\in A\text{,}\) then \(A\) contains a greatest element.
The element
\(l\) in
Theorem 4.39 is referred to as a
lower bound for
\(A\) while the element
\(u\) in
Theorem 4.40 is called an
upper bound for
\(A\text{.}\) We will study lower and upper bounds in more detail in
Section 5.1.
Life is like riding a bicycle. To keep your balance you must keep moving.
―Albert Einstein, theoretical physicist